Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

A World Destroyed: Hiroshima and Its Legacies, Third Edition
A World Destroyed: Hiroshima and Its Legacies, Third Edition
A World Destroyed: Hiroshima and Its Legacies, Third Edition
Ebook578 pages8 hours

A World Destroyed: Hiroshima and Its Legacies, Third Edition

Rating: 4 out of 5 stars

4/5

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Continuously in demand since its first, prize-winning edition was published in 1975, this is the classic history of the development of the American atomic bomb, the decision to use it against Japan, and the origins of U.S. atomic diplomacy toward the Soviet Union.

In his Preface to this new edition, the author describes and evaluates the lengthening trail of new evidence that has come to light concerning these often emotionally debated subjects. The author also invokes his experience as a historical advisor to the controversial, aborted 1995 Enola Gay exhibit at the National Air and Space Museum of the Smithsonian Institution. This leads him to analyze the impact on American democracy of one of the most insidious of the legacies of Hiroshima: the political control of historical interpretation.

Reviews of Previous Editions

"The quality of Sherwin's research and the strength of his argument are far superior to previous accounts."

New York Times Book Review

"Probably the definitive account for a long time to come. . . . Sherwin has tackled some of the critical questions of the Cold War's origins—and has settled them, in my opinion."

—Walter LaFeber,

Cornell University

"One of those rare achievements of conscientious scholarship, a book at once graceful and luminous, yet loyal to its documentation and restrained in its speculations."

Boston Globe

LanguageEnglish
Release dateAug 19, 2003
ISBN9781503618930
A World Destroyed: Hiroshima and Its Legacies, Third Edition
Author

Martin J. Sherwin

Martin J. Sherwin is Professor of History at Tufts University abd University Professor at George Mason University. He is the author of A World Destroyed: Hiroshima and its Legacies and, with Kai Bird, of the Pulitzer Prize winner American Prometheus: The Triumph and Tragedy of J. Robert Oppenheimer (Atlantic 2008). He and his wife live in Washington, D.C.

Read more from Martin J. Sherwin

Related to A World Destroyed

Related ebooks

Wars & Military For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for A World Destroyed

Rating: 4 out of 5 stars
4/5

9 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    A World Destroyed - Martin J. Sherwin

    A WORLD DESTROYED

    HIROSHIMA AND ITS LEGACIES

    THIRD EDITION

    MARTIN J. SHERWIN

    With a foreword by Robert J. Lifton

    STANFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS

    Stanford, California 2003

    Copyright © 1973, 1975, by Martin J. Sherwin;

    Introduction to Stanford edition © 2003 Martin J. Sherwin.

    Introduction to third edition copyright © 1987 by Martin J. Sherwin

    Originally published by Alfred A. Knopf, 1973;

    Vintage edition, 1987; reissued by Stanford University Press 2003

    All rights reserved.

    Printed in the United States of America on acid-free, archival-quality paper

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Sherwin, Martin J.

    A world destroyed : Hiroshima and the origins of the arms race / Martin J. Sherwin.—3rd ed.

       p.    cm.

    Includes bibliographical references and index.

    ISBN 0-8047-3957-9 (pbk. : alk. paper)

    ISBN 978-0-8047-3957-3 (paper)

    ISBN 978-1-5036-1893-0 (ebook)

    1. World politics—1945-1989.

    2. Nuclear warfare—United States.

    3. Arms race—History—20th century.

    4. Hiroshima-shi (Japan)—History—Bombardment, 1945.

    5. Nagasaki-shi (Japan)—History—Bombardment, 1945.

    I. Title.

    D842 .S49   2004

    940.53'2273—dC22      2003014107

    Portions of this book were previously published in The American Historical Review.

    Grateful acknowledgment is made to Yale University Library for material from the Henry Lewis Stimson Papers, Manuscripts and Archives; and to Henry Holt & Company for the poems U.S. 1946 King’s X, The Road Not Taken, Fire and Ice, and The Secret Sits from The Poetry of Robert Frosty edited by Edward Connery Lathem. Copyright 1916, 1923, 1947, © 1969 by Holt, Rinehart & Winston, Inc. Copyright 1942, 1944, 1951 by Robert Frost. Copyright © 1970, 1975 by Lesley Frost Ballantine.

    For

    Mimi and Harold

    Susan, Andrea, and Alex

    U.S. 1946 KING’S X

    Having invented a new Holocaust,

    And been the first with it to win a war,

    How they make haste to cry with fingers crossed,

    King’s X—no fairs to use it any more!

    —ROBERT FROST

    CONTENTS

    Foreword by Robert J. Lifton

    Preface to the Third Edition

    Introduction to the 1987 Edition

    Notes to the Introduction to the 1987 Edition

    Acknowledgments

    INTRODUCTION

    I: THE SECRET SITS

    1. THE END OF THE BEGINNING

    2. SOLDIERS OUT OF UNIFORM

    II: THE ROAD NOT TAKEN

    3. THE ATOMIC BOMB AND THE POSTWAR WORLD

    4. THE TWO POLICEMEN

    5. A QUID PRO QUO

    III: FIRE AND ICE

    6. THE NEW PRESIDENT

    7. PERSUADING RUSSIA TO PLAY BALL

    8. THE BOMB, THE WAR, AND THE RUSSIANS

    9. DIPLOMACY—AND DESTRUCTION

    Notes

    On Primary Sources in the Field: A Bibliographical Essay

    Appendices: Selected Documents

    Index

    FOREWORD

    Robert J. Lifton

    Human beings are meaning-hungry creatures. We have the need to bring special significance to objects and events in order to become part of a narrative that is larger than ourselves. In the case of the atomic bomb, the object and the event defied our imaginative grasp. Small wonder that the meanings we have assigned to the weapon have been infused with a constellation of awe and mystery. That constellation has included tendencies to embrace the bomb, to become fiercely dependent upon it, indeed, to render it something close to a deity. For what other than a deity could be capable of destroying the world?

    But a deity also must be capable of ruling and protecting the world, even of keeping the world going. Hence, the bizarre emphasis on die bomb’s ostensible function of saving lives rather than destroying them, of rendering die world peaceful rather than bringing to it a specter of annihilation.

    This worshipful embrace of the cruelest weapon ever created is the essence of what I call nuclearism, which is surely the most depraved spiritual malady of our era.

    The remarkable achievement of Martin Sherwin’s classic study is to reveal the beginnings of nuclearism at the moment of the appearance of the atomic bomb and, before that, in the excited anticipation of die revolutionary new object’s potential.

    We learn that even ethically sensitive leaders—statesmen, military leaders, and scientists—advocated the use of the bomb. Early on, both Leo Szilard and Niels Bohr, distinguished scientists who were to become justifiably renowned for their opposition to nuclear weapons, took the position during World War II that only by witnessing its destructive effects would the people of the world become so appalled that future wars could be averted. And Secretary of War Henry L. Stimson, a man sufficiently humane to have single-handedly prevented the targeting of Kyoto, Japan’s magnificent ancient capital, argued that a successful atomic attack on a Japanese city would influence Stalin to be more cooperative in postwar negotiations. These two anticipatory attitudes toward nuclear weapons suggest that an idealistic aura of peacemaking was inseparable from the bomb’s lure of ultimate technology and ultimate power—all of which became part of the transcendent ideology of nuclearism.

    Versions of nuclearism have haunted the world ever since. The recent successful tests of nuclear weapons in India and Pakistan were disturbing not only in their clear evidence of dangerous nuclear proliferation, but in the exuberance of leaders and citizens of both countries as they celebrated their entry into the omnipotent realm of potential world destroyers. And the weapons’ attraction is not limited to nations. During the 1990s, the relatively small Japanese cult Aun Shinrikyo succeeded in manufacturing biological and chemical weapons as a substitute for the nuclear weapons they most passionately (though, fortunately, unsuccessfully) coveted. This worldwide tendency to what can be called trickle-down nuclearism is made possible not only by the increasing availability of nuclear materials and information about their design, but by the transmission of the allure of these weapons to ever smaller groups.

    The most egregious manifestations of nuclearism, however, come from our own political leaders. They are bound up with what can be called our superpower syndrome, our insistence that we remain unchallenged in our world military dominance. The superpower syndrome includes consistent unilateralism in international behavior, the self-bestowed right to determine who may pursue work on the weapons and who may not, and even the right to engage in preemptive—or preventive—war if we decide that a country is a danger to us. Predominant nuclear superiority is the basis for both the superpower’s absolute military dominance and its dark mystique.

    Beyond their insistence on nuclear dominance, American leaders have expressed a shockingly candid willingness to use the weapons. Their emphasis has been not on eliminating the scourge of nuclear weapons but on seeking more innovative ways to make them effective, for instance, in destroying underground bunkers. There is the increasing danger of what Richard Falk calls the Hiroshima temptation, of deciding to employ a small nuclear weapon against a country that cannot retaliate because it possesses no nuclear weapons. Since the mind engulfed by nuclearism never rests, we can expect ever more imaginative ideas about how generations of improved nuclear weapons can be employed.

    In his riveting description of the end of our prenuclear world and the emergence of nuclearism, Martin Sherwin makes clear that this spiritual deformation need not be our fate. But if we are to find wiser psychological and political directions, we need to draw upon the insights he provides about the origins of our malady.

    PREFACE TO THE THIRD EDITION

    Martin J. Sherwin

    Many of the basic issues related to the future of atomic weapons first discussed in A World Destroyed more than 25 years ago were argued in secret during World War II, and they have been debated in public with increasing ferocity ever since. In 1994–1995, as the fiftieth anniversary of the end of that war approached, the debate over the atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki reached a new apogee (or, perhaps more properly, an unprecedented nadir) in a political controversy over the National Air and Space Museum’s plan to accompany the display of the recently refurbished fuselage of the Enola, Gay (the B-29 that dropped the first atomic bomb on Hiroshima) with an exhibit based on decades of historical scholarship.

    It is one of the ironies of that controversy that the eventual Congressional censorship of this historical exhibit (in part for acknowledging information and documents published earlier in A World Destroyed) drew national attention to the research that the Air Force Association, the American Legion, and many senators and representatives found objectionable. In writing about this clash of politics and history, the mainstream press generally continued to accept the idea that the atomic bombings were necessary, but simultaneously acknowledged that for fifty years the American public had been misled about the history of the decision-making process. Thus, during the celebratory summer and fall of 1995, as millions of visitors to the Air and Space Museum viewed the Enola Gay and a videotaped interview with its pilot, readers of the establishment weekly Newsweek learned more about the so-called revisionist case than they would have learned if the first, and much maligned script, The Crossroads: The End of World War II, the Atomic Bomb and the Origins of the Cold War, had become die basis for the Enola Gay exhibit.*

    No doubt the lessons of this incident are debatable, but one thing seems certain: in 1995 the history of 1945 remained hostage to politics, and how that history is written counts in the culture wars that continuously redefine America.

    The debate that surrounded the historical segment of the Enola Gay exhibit is not only a pointed example of a clash between politics and history. It is also a poignant lesson about the role of memory, the politics of history, and the political uses of history. Even in the twenty-first century American culture continues to live in the shadow of World War II. This is so not only because personal memories of the war remain a part of the debate over its history, but because a particular vision of the war has become central to a certain cultural American mystique.

    In the United States, the collective memory of World War II sees the war as our finest hour. In Europe, we vanquished a cruel and dangerous fascism. In Asia, we destroyed a virulent military machine. After victory we were magnanimous: we fed our former enemies, put them back on their economic feet, and tutored them in democracy. In the American collective memory, World War II was not simply the good war; it was the model for the perfect American war. It was a just war, a righteous war, and, as leaflets dropped on Japanese cities in July 1945 stated, it was a war in which America stood for humanity.

    America without that image is unimaginable to most members of the generation that fought the war and to those in subsequent generations who have defined their view of the world and their political lives as a reflection of this image. It is not surprising, therefore, that historical research that reveals a different perspective on American actions—actions such as the atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki—should be culturally indigestible, politically unacceptable, and deeply resented. That was the reality of the underlying Enola Gay controversy.

    The political attitudes engendered by the Cold War powerfully reinforced this reality. The image of American moral superiority was promoted relendessly during the Cold War, and our increasing reliance on nuclear deterrence created another dimension of hostility to criticism of the wartime use of nuclear weapons. Early questions about the necessity of destroying Hiroshima and Nagasaki were replaced by official answers that left no room for ambiguity.

    American society has an especially strong intolerance for ambiguity, and that intolerance has always affected the public’s attitude toward nuanced academic scholarship. Perhaps it results from our system of government, which, in contrast to a parliamentary system, severely limits the spectrum of views we debate. Our public dialogues are driven toward simplification and clarity. More than in other democratic societies, our problems are discussed in either/or terms: good or bad, right or wrong. Ambiguity and complexity are unwelcome, even viewed with suspicion, in our political culture.

    Unlike any other American war, World War II was unambiguously right, a war with clarity of purpose and an unprecedented shared sense of national unity. But victory left an ambiguous legacy—our relationship with our erstwhile Soviet ally. The Cold War may have been a poor substitute for World War II, but World War II was an ideal model for the Cold War (and, as of this writing, for President George W. Bush’s war on terrorism). The demand for clarity drove our politics, and our politics eliminated ambiguity. Stalin substituted for Hitler, Communism replaced National Socialism, and Soviet cities were targeted as so many Hiroshimas and Nagasakis. Memories of World War II coexisted comfortably with the perceived requirements of the Cold War, stifling any serious critical discussion of why all the alternatives that had been proposed to the atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki had been rejected.

    Research into die history of the atomic bombings is framed necessarily by two distinct questions that are often conflated and then confused with each other. The first question is fundamentally a study of the relationship between ideas and policy: Why did the United States government decide to use atomic bombs against Japan in August 1945? Answers to that question can only be found in the archives of the United States. It is in the memoranda, diaries, letters, notes, and recollections of officials of the Roosevelt and Truman administrations that the historian can discover what the key decision-makers and their advisors (official and unofficial) believed were the purposes and consequences of the atomic bombing of Japanese cities. (In a famous question posed during the Watergate hearings, What did the president know and when did he know it? One must also ask, What did his advisors think and why did they think it?) This book addresses those questions directly and in detail.

    The second broad question leads the historian to archives in Tokyo: Could Japan have been induced to surrender at about the same time (or even earlier) without the use of atomic bombs? Or, to ask the same question in a slightly different way: Were one or both of the atomic bombings necessary to convince the Japanese to surrender in August 1945?

    As will become clear in the pages that follow, there were high-level members of the Departments of State and War who in June and July 1945 argued that decrypted Japanese diplomatic messages made it clear that Japan would surrender only if and when the United States guaranteed the safety of Emperor Hirohito. Many of these officials, and others, also believed that Soviet entry into the war against Japan would precipitate Japan’s capitulation, a result that was viewed as an unwelcome gift. Almost all members of the Truman administration wished to avoid, if possible, such an obvious Soviet contribution to the end of the Pacific war.

    Thus, the issues that would come to dominate the public debate over the necessity, the consequences, and the wisdom of using atomic bombs against Japan after the war began months before Hiroshima and Nagasaki were destroyed. But after those bombings occurred the nature of the debate was altered in two ways. In the first instance, the debate became inextricably linked to, and controlled by, the exigencies of the Cold War. And, second, while those controls and exigencies continued to exert pressure to maintain the official narrative,** historians were gaining access to previously classified documents that suggested explanations more convincing than those first presented by members of the Roosevelt and Truman administrations. Perhaps not surprisingly, by the 1970s, after decades of declassification and research, historians had more information about the full range of the decision-making process that led to the destruction of Hiroshima and Nagasaki than any of the participants had had in 1945.

    Thus, the study of the decisions associated with the first use of nuclear weapons is a classic example of two important historical phenomena: (1) die way a nation’s political culture influences the public acceptance of historical research; and (2) the way historical perspective not only clarifies the consequences of an event but may also provide a clearer understanding of how and why the event occurred. The revision of history, in other words, is at the very heart of the historian’s search for a deeper and more accurate understanding of the past. This reality appears to have been politically unacceptable in 1995 during the Enola Gay debate; it remains a question whether it is acceptable today.

    Notes

    * Newsweek. July 24, 1995, Why We Did It, pp. 22–30. The article acknowledges such previously controversial points as that (1) General Leslie Groves, the military commander of the atomic project, was determined to demonstrate the power of what he called ‘the gadget’ (p. 23); (2) Secretary of War Henry L. Stimson saw the bomb as a ‘mastercard’ in the great game of diplomacy (p. 25); (3) the Japanese were trying to surrender on condition that the Emperor’s safety be guaranteed (p. 26); (4) from a military perspective, there was no particular urgency to end the war right away (p. 26); (5) President Truman engaged himself in some comforting psychological denial by claiming that a military base rather than women and children had been the target (p. 27); (6) that "Hirohito had decided to surrender before Nagasaki (p. 28); and (7) After some semantic dithering over the meaning of unconditional surrender, the Allies agreed to allow Hirohito to keep his throne after all, in order to get the war over with" (p. 28).

    ** Henry L. Stimson, The Decision to Use the Atomic Bomb, Harper’s Magazine, February 1947, vol. 1161, pp. 97–107.

    INTRODUCTION TO THE 1987 EDITION

    Reflections on the First Nuclear War

    The facts of history are . . . not about the motives, real or imaginary, from which individuals suppose themselves to have acted. They are facts about the relations of individuals to one another in society and about the social forces which produce from the actions of individuals results often at variance with, and sometimes opposite to, the results which they themselves intended.

    —E. H. CARR¹

    On July 16, 1945, dawn broke twice over the Alamagordo desert in New Mexico. At 5:30 A.M., thirty minutes before the sun rose, science preempted nature with a lighting effect . . . equal to several suns at midday.² Just five and a half years after the discovery of nuclear fission, Manhattan Project scientists had constructed and successfully tested an atomic bomb. By raising the consequences of war to the level of Armageddon, the atomic bomb elevated the stakes of peace beyond historical experience. In physicist I. I. Rabi’s cryptic phrase: Suddenly the day of judgment was the next day and has been ever since.³

    From the earliest days of the Manhattan Project, that apocalyptic vision has shaped the debate over nuclear weapons. On one side of the argument are those who insist that the dangers inherent in large nuclear arsenals overwhelm any need for their existence. Focusing on the consequences of a nuclear war, those who argue this case have sought to minimize the number of nuclear weapons and deemphasize their military and diplomatic roles.

    On the other side of the debate are those who view the dangers inherent in nuclear weapons as both a guarantor of U.S. national security and as an effective instrument of diplomatic and military power. Impressed by the logic of nuclear deterrence, adherents of this point of view have sought to maximize both the quality and quantity of nuclear weapons in the U.S. arsenal and to promote their military and diplomatic utility.

    The assumptions and attitudes that support these opposing views were formulated in secrecy during World War II. At its beginning they were implicit in the discussions that led to the decision to build atomic bombs. Near the end of the war they were made explicit in the discussions that led to their use against urban targets. The fiery atomic spectacles that marked the war’s conclusion marked, too, the debate’s first and most important resolution.

    Indeed, many of the most powerful forces that have shaped the postwar world were unleashed by the mushroom clouds that rose over Japan in August 1945: the beginning of the nuclear arms race and the possible extinction of the human race; the moral sway of American power and the ability of technology to overwhelm morality; the conflicting ambitions of the wartime allies and the mutual interests of former enemies. For these reasons, Hiroshima marked a beginning not an end, though it remains a point of sharp contention as to whether its destruction ended the possibility of a more hopeful start to the nuclear age.

    The circumstances and considerations that led to the atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki are addressed throughout A World Destroyed. But since its original publication, I have become increasingly interested in the relationship between the wartime history of the atomic bomb and the postwar nuclear arms race—between the assumptions and attitudes that justified urban bombing as a strategy for winning the war, and the arguments and expectations that have rationalized nuclear deterrence as an instrument of American policy ever since. These considerations have prompted me to revise the subtitle for this new edition (the original subtitle was The Atomic Bomb and the Grand Alliance) and to explore in this new Introduction some of the legacies of what we must learn to recognize as the first nuclear war.

    • • •

    In 1983 I. I. Rabi spoke at the Los Alamos Scientific Laboratory during the fortieth-anniversary reunion marking the founding of the facility, where the bombs dropped on Hiroshima and Nagasaki were designed and assembled. History is a very important thing, he said, because by perusal of history you see the greatness and the folly of humanity.⁴ The history of the Manhattan Project was his case in point. The scientists who constructed those weapons at Los Alamos had been drawn to the task in order to save Western civilization from fascism, by building an atomic bomb before the Germans. Then, on the eve of success, they undertook to save civilization from the atomic bomb itself, by devising formulas to prevent a nuclear arms race.* But, to borrow the historian E. H. Carr’s words, the outcome was opposite to the results which they themselves intended.

    Most students of this subject are aware of the numerous ironies associated with the rescue efforts launched by the atomic scientists at the end of the war and during its immediate aftermath. But one ironic twist that has gone almost unnoticed is particularly poignant: virtually all of the basic ideas associated with nuclear weapons today—many of them ideas that have contributed to nuclear escalation and proliferation—derive from attitudes, assumptions, and expectations formulated during the war for the purpose of preventing a nuclear arms race afterward.

    The nuclear bargaining chip for arms control negotiations, a concept first suggested by James B. Conant in 1944, was adopted in 1946 by Bernard Baruch, who presented the U.S. plan for the international control of atomic energy to the United Nations. Nuclear intimidation, the psychological premise of nuclear containment, was anticipated in 1945 at the atomic bomb targeting committee meetings in Los Alamos. Limited nuclear war, an idea first popularized in 1958 by Henry Kissinger’s Nuclear Weapons and Foreign Policy and then adopted in 1980 as Presidential Directive-59 by the Carter Administration, was discussed during the war as an integral part of the effort to bring the Soviet Union to accept the international control of atomic energy. A strategic defense against nuclear weapons was first raised in 1942 by Arthur Compton, who urged a crash program for researching and developing counter measures against a German atomic bomb. Deterrence, and even the warning shot strategy, were concepts implicit in the decisions that led to the destruction of Hiroshima and Nagasaki.

    The more we reflect upon these historical origins, the more disquieting are the reverberations of the title Rabi chose for his speech: How Well We Meant.

    Hiroshima as Moral History

    More than four decades after the destruction of Hiroshima and Nagasaki, the relevance of the fate of those cities has not diminished, nor have the debates they ignited. No one who looks closely at those debates will fail to recognize that there are issues at stake that go beyond military history. There are questions of morality, national character, and this nation’s responsibility for the shape of the postwar world. Hiroshima not only introduced the nuclear age, it also served as the symbolic coronation of U.S. global power. The atomic bomb, as more than one contemporary cartoonist depicted it, was our scepter, and its use contributed to the image of our international authority.

    But military power was not the only foundation for authority. The position of the United States as a great humanitarian nation was also important, Under Secretary of the Navy Ralph Bard wrote to the Secretary of War on June 27, 1945,*. Urging that the Japanese be warned several days prior to the attack, Bard sought to modify the decision taken on May 31 that we could not give the Japanese any warning; that we could not concentrate on a civilian area; but that we should seek to make a profound psychological impression on as many of the inhabitants as possible. At the suggestion of Dr. [James B.] Conant the Secretary [of War Henry L. Stimson) agreed, the minutes of the Interim Committee continued: the most desirable target would be a vital war plant employing a large number of workers and closely surrounded by workers' houses (emphasis added).*

    Bard’s advice went unheeded, however, and an early irony of Hiroshima was that the very act symbolizing our wartime victory was quickly turned against our peacetime purposes. At the 1946–1948 Tokyo War Crimes Trials, which, like the Nuremberg trials, were a symbolic expression of our moral authority, Justice Radhabinod Pal of India cited Hiroshima and Nagasaki as evidence against our claim to rule by right of superior virtue. The atomic bombings, he wrote in a dissenting opinion, were the only near approach [in the Pacific War] to the directive . . . of the Nazi leaders during the Second World War.

    President Truman’s earliest public explanations for the bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki addressed the issues of just cause and morality that Pal later raised. We have used [the atomic bomb], he stated, in order to shorten the agony of war, in order to save the lives of thousands and thousands of young Americans.⁶ But several days later he added less lofty reasons. Responding to a telegram criticizing the atomic bombings, the President wrote:

    Nobody is more disturbed over the use of Atomic bombs than I am but I was greatly disturbed over the unwarranted attack by the Japanese on Pearl Harbor and their murder of our prisoners of war. The only language they seem to understand is the one we have been using to bombard them.

    When you have to deal with a beast you have to treat him as a beast. It is most regrettable but nevertheless true.

    But in the aftermath of Hiroshima, many thoughtful commentators began to view the bomb itself as the beast. For all we know, H. V. Kaltenborn, the dean of radio news commentators, observed on August 7, we have created a Frankenstein! We must assume that with the passage of only a little time, an improved form of the new weapon we use today can be turned against us.

    At some level, this thought has been the enduring night-mare of the nuclear age, a vision of an inevitable holocaust imbedded deep within our culture. How does the universe end? Billy Pilgrim, the protagonist in Kurt Vonnegut’s Slaughterhouse Five, asks his omniscient Trafalmadorian captors. The novel continues:

    We blow it up, experimenting with new fuels for our flying saucers. A Trafalmadorian test pilot presses a starter button, and the whole Universe disappears.

    If you know this, said Billy, isn’t there some way you can prevent it? Can’t you keep the pilot from pressing the button?

    He has always pressed it, and he always will. We always let him and we always will let him. The moment is structured that way.

    The structure of the nuclear age—deterrence and the inexorable accumulation of the weapons designed to promote its purposes—has encouraged a deadening sense that there are forces at work beyond political control. The American public’s feeling of powerlessness before those forces may be the single most important reason behind the belief that a massive arsenal of nuclear weapons is needed to guarantee our national security. Even here, the moral dimension of the debate over the atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki is relevant, for it is of paramount importance to those who wish to rely upon nuclear weapons that they are not tarnished with a sense of guilt that could inhibit their use as an instrument of diplomacy.

    This concern about the practical effects of Hiroshima guilt was discussed soon after the war by the Manhattan Project’s chief science administrator, James Conant, who had returned full time to his post as president of Harvard University. Raising the issue in a letter to former Secretary of War Henry L. Stimson, he wrote of his concern about the spreading accusation that it was entirely unnecessary to use the atomic bomb at all, particularly among those he described as verbal minded citizens not so generally influential as they were influential among the coming generations of whom they might be teachers or educators. To combat that view, he urged Stimson to write an article on the decision to use the bomb, which subsequently appeared in the February 1947 issue of Harper's magazine.¹⁰

    If the propaganda against the use of the atomic bomb had been allowed to grow unchecked, Conant wrote to Stimson after reading a prepublication version of the article, the strength of our military position by virtue of having the bomb would have been correspondingly weakened, and the chances for international control undermined. Humanitarian considerations that led citizens to oppose the strengthening of the U.S. atomic arsenal, in Conant’s opinion, were likely to subvert the common effort to achieve an international atomic energy agreement. I am firmly convinced, he told Stimson, "that the Russians will eventually agree to the American proposals for the establishment of an atomic energy authority of world-wide scope, provided they are convinced that we would have the bomb in quantity and would use it without hesitation in another war."¹¹

    Stimson’s article responded to Conant’s practical concerns. Explaining the steps in the decision strictly in the context of the Pacific War and the objective of avoiding the enormous losses of human life which otherwise confronted us, he left no room for the suggestion that considerations beyond the war could have been factors, or that in future similar circumstances the government would not be compelled to take similar actions. The war had not ended when the bomb became available; the decision flowed inexorably out of those circumstances: In light of the alternatives which, on a fair estimate, were open to us I believe that no man, in our position and subject to our responsibilities, Stimson wrote, holding in his hands a weapon of such possibilities, could have failed to use it and afterwards looked his countrymen in the face.¹²

    The primary argument for the necessity of using the atomic bomb was saving American lives. President Truman wrote in his memoirs that half a million U.S. soldiers would have been killed had the planned invasions been launched. Winston Churchill claimed that the figure was closer to a million.¹³ Could any responsible Commander-in-Chief send so many young men to die on foreign shores when an alternative like the atomic bomb was readily at hand?

    As stated, the question answers itself. As stated, it also distorts the nature of the historical problem. Before the decision to use atomic bombs can be properly understood, many other questions need to be considered. They range from the expected impact of the use of the bomb on the Japanese during the war to the influence such a demonstration might have on the Soviet behavior afterward. They include questions related to bureaucratic momentum and political expediency; to the instinct for revenge as well as the pressure for results; to scientific pride and economic investments; to Roosevelt’s legacy and Truman’s insecurity.

    In the original edition of A World Destroyed I sought to analyze these questions within their historical context, limiting the discussion to what was said and done before the bombs were dropped. My narrative tacitly accepted the published casualty estimates as a compelling influence limiting decision makers’ choices. But recently discovered estimates of invasion casualties dramatically contradict the figures released by Truman, Churchill, and Stimson. These require some comments on the information that has shaped the postwar debate.

    Historians have known for decades that several alternatives to atomic bombing or an invasion of Japan were considered during May and June 1945.¹⁴ The first was to modify unconditional surrender. Having broken the Japanese diplomatic code, the Department of State’s Far Eastern specialists were sanguine that the peace advocates in the Imperial Cabinet could win capitulation if the United States assured Japan that it would maintain the Emperor and the Imperial Dynasty. The second alternative was to delay the atomic bombings until after August 8, the final day on which Stalin could live up to his agreement to enter the war against Japan within three months after Germany’s surrender.* The third alternative, Admiral William D. Leahy wrote to the Joint Chiefs of Staff on June 14, 1945, was to defeat Japan by isolation, blockade, and bombardment by sea and air forces.

    All of these suggestions were viable alternatives, but none of them was without its particular disadvantages.

    The first option, modifying unconditional surrender, was politically risky. Introduced by Roosevelt and accepted by the Allies, the unconditional surrender had become the basis upon which the public expected the war to be concluded. From the point of view of Truman and his advisers, tampering with this doctrine appeared fraught with unattractive political dangers.

    Second, a Japanese surrender (precipitous or otherwise) following the entry of the Soviet Union into the Pacific War would have facilitated the expansion of Soviet power in the Far East. By the summer of 1945 such an option was anathema to Truman and his advisers.

    Finally, continuing the blockade and bombardment promised no immediate results and might, as the Joint War Plans Committee wrote to the President, have an adverse effect upon the U.S. position vis-à-vis other nations who will, in the meantime, be rebuilding their peacetime economy.*

    In the summer of 1945 it was therefore not the lack of an alternative that might induce Japan’s surrender that led to the use of atomic bombs. It was the undesirability of relying on the available alternatives given the nuclear option. The nuclear option was preferred because it promised dividends—not just the possibility that it would end the war but the hope that it would eliminate the need to rely on one of the other alternatives.

    The question of how policymakers came to understand their choices is probed throughout A World Destroyed. It is a question we should keep before us as the recent discovery of the actual invasion casualty estimates should make clear. The casualty estimates announced by Truman in the aftermath of Hiroshima were grossly exaggerated, as documents reproduced in Appendix U demonstrate. For example, on June 15, 1945, the Joint War Plans Committee (JWPC) estimated that about 40,000 Americans would be killed and 150,000 wounded if both southern Kyushu and the Tokyo plain had to be invaded (on November 1, 1945, and March 1, 1946, respectively).¹⁵ General George C. Marshall, Army Chief of Staff, who Truman cited in his memoirs as the source of the estimate that an invasion would cost half a million American lives, endorsed an estimate on June 7 that was similar to the one produced a week later by the Joint War Plans Committee.¹⁶ On June 18, General Douglas Mac-Arthur, the commander of U.S. Pacific forces, concurred with the range of JWPC’s estimates.¹⁷ On July 9 a memorandum to the Joint Staff Planners entitled Note by the Secretaries included a revised casualty estimate of 31,000 killed, wounded, and missing for the first 30 days of the planned operation against Kyushu.†

    In the end the most destructive conventional war of the century was concluded with the first nuclear warfare in history. Many who advocated that alternative hoped it would contribute to a postwar settlement that would banish those weapons—others hoped it would establish their value. But whatever they believed, those who felt called upon to defend the bombing of Hiroshima and Nagasaki came to recognize more clearly in retrospect what a few had warned in prospect: that nuclear war was beyond the reach of conventional moral categories.

    Though no American President could be expected to have chosen an invasion of Japan if a plausible alternative was available, the fact that several available alternatives had been rejected increased the moral burden of justifying the extraordinary consequences of Hiroshima and Nagasaki. Americans had self-consciously fought World War II to preserve the values of their civilization. Is it surprising that in its aftermath those who had directed the war conspired to explain its terrible conclusion as unavoidable and consistent with those values?

    Reflecting on the choices the administration had faced in the summer of 1945, former Secretary of War Stimson felt compelled to admit the possibility that refusing to modify unconditional surrender might have been a mistake—a mistake that could have delayed the end of the war. Composing his memoirs several years after the war, he wrote that history might find that the United States, by its delay in stating its position [on the conditions of surrender], had prolonged the war.¹⁸

    Despite Stimson’s singular remark, and the general availability of information about the other options, the invasion has remained the alternative to the atomic bombings in public discussions. Perhaps this is because the invasion remains the least ambiguous of the options. Or perhaps it is because it lends to the bombings an implicit moral legitimacy. According to the figures released, the magnitude of the projected slaughter of invading Americans was even greater than the actual slaughter of Japanese civilians. As reports, images, and tales of death, dying, and suffering from nuclear warfare filtered into the American press, the alternatives to the invasion were filtered out.¹⁹

    The manipulation of the estimated casualty figures, and thereby the history of the decision-making process that led to the atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki, has masked an important lesson. The choice in the summer of 1945 was not between a conventional invasion or a nuclear war. It was a choice between various forms of diplomacy and warfare. While the decision that Truman made is understandable, it was not inevitable. It was even avoidable. In the end, that is the most important legacy of Hiroshima for the nuclear age.

    Los Alamos and Hiroshima

    The confluence of the invention of weapons that could destroy the world and a foreign policy of global proportions removed the physical and psychological barriers that had protected the United States from the full force of international affairs before World War II. In the context of the cold war, politics no longer stopped at the water’s edge. On the contrary, politics often began there. No group of Americans was more alert to this change than the scientists of the Manhattan Project, who had brought it about. To Robert Oppenheimer, the new alignment of science and power threatened the life of science [and] the life of the world. The change in scale and stakes involved scientists more, he said, than any other group in the world. The existence of the atomic bomb linked science to national security and made scientists into military assets. The twin evils of secrecy and control strike at the very roots of what science is and what it is for, Oppenheimer warned his former colleagues at Los Alamos in November 1945.²⁰

    The question of the meaning and uses of science raised by Oppenheimer took on a new sense of immediacy for all scientists after the war. With the advent of the atomic age, the answer to the question of science and the state inevitably became tied to the political and national defense issues generated by the cold war. As a result, the boundary between science and politics blurred, and the public’s attitude toward science was increasingly defined by political criteria. In such an environment Bernard Baruch could suggest that science should be free but only when the world has been freed from the menaces which hang over us.²¹

    The scientists disagreed. Fearing that science would become the first political victim of their success, Percy W. Bridgman, the president of the American Physical Society, responded to the threat of external control of science with the declaration that society is the servant of science. . . . Any control which society exerts over science and invention must be subject to this condition.²²

    With Bridgman, the scientist’s, view at one pole and the converse approach expressed by Baruch at the other, it is not too much to suggest that there arose a split between two cultures. But it was not, as C. P. Snow argued, a division having to do with a nonscientist’s knowledge of the second law of thermodynamics or a scientist’s ability to quote Shakespeare. It touched upon a deeper issue—the nature of freedom and power in a democratic society.

    Oppenheimer spoke of this issue from a scientific perspective in answering the question he had raised. If you are a scientist, he said, you believe that it is good to find out how the world works . . . that it is good to turn over to mankind at large the greatest possible power to control the world and to deal with it according to its lights and its values. It was not for the scientist to judge, he implied, whether those lights and values were adequate to control new understandings. Nor was it for society to judge, he added explicitly, what the scientist should and should not seek to discover. Any such external control is based on a philosophy incompatible with that by which we live, and have learned to live in the past.²³ If society was not the servant of science, it certainly was a collaborator. To politicize science was to destroy it. A free state could only be well served by science if scientists were free to publish and discuss their research. A state was not free, he implied, if the life of science was not open and free of political control.

    To keep politics out of science, scientists responded politically. Some counseled the Administration privately against policies that would lead to military control, while others led a successful campaign against military domination of the Atomic Energy Commission. However, in the ensuing cold war, civilian control of atomic energy proved to be illusory. Military requirements held sway, loyalty and security programs were vigorously enforced, and government support led to far more control than anticipated. Though scientists gained greater opportunities to participate in policy formulation, their advice was expected to support basic policies decided by others. This was the clear message communicated by the removal of Oppenheimer’s security clearance in 1954.²⁴

    After the war, the scientific community itself appeared to divide culturally. Scientists such as Oppenheimer, Vannevar Bush, James Conant, Ernest Lawrence, and Karl and Arthur Compton worked closely with the government.

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1