Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Universities: The Recovery of an Idea
Universities: The Recovery of an Idea
Universities: The Recovery of an Idea
Ebook191 pages2 hours

Universities: The Recovery of an Idea

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Research assessment exercises, teaching quality assessment, line management, staff appraisal, student course evaluation, modularization, student fees - these are all names of innovations (and problems) - in modern British universities. How far do they reflect a more conscientious approach to the effective promotion of higher education, and how far do they constitute a significant departure from traditional academic concerns and values? Using some themes of Cardinal Newman's classic The Idea of a University as a springboard, this extended essay aims to address these questions.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateNov 6, 2013
ISBN9781845407407
Universities: The Recovery of an Idea

Related to Universities

Related ebooks

Teaching Methods & Materials For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Universities

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Universities - Gordon Graham

    Title page

    Universities

    The Recovery of an Idea

    Gordon Graham

    IMPRINT ACADEMIC

    Copyright page

    2013 digital version by Andrews UK Limited

    www.andrewsuk.com

    Copyright © Gordon Graham, 2002

    The moral rights of the author have been asserted

    No part of any contribution may be reproduced in any form without permission, except for the quotation of brief passages in criticism and discussion.

    Published in the UK by Imprint Academic

    PO Box 1, Thorverton EX5 5YX, UK

    Published in the USA by Imprint Academic

    Philosophy Documentation Center

    PO Box 7147, Charlottesville, VA 22906-7147, USA

    Preface

    The first version of this book was written almost five years ago, but was unable to find a publisher. I approached no fewer than eleven and all of them said that academic interest is now so specialized, no one would be interested in reading what is essentially an academic book about universities in general. In the belief, or at least the hope, that this could not be so, I produced copies for distribution to people I thought might be interested. It was picked up and included in the Booknotes section of the journal Philosophy, and as a result I had quite a number of requests for copies, a number sufficient to suggest that the publishers were wrong about the level of interest. I would like to record my thanks to all those who wrote to me appreciatively about my attempt to prompt a debate about modern British universities that would avoid partisanship and employ the same sort of standards that the best academic inquiry prides itself on.

    Eventually, by good fortune I encountered an interested publisher. This gave me the opportunity to revise the text, to note the appearance in the meantime of The New Idea of a University by Duke Maskell and Ian Robinson, and to update the sections on teaching quality, research assessment and student fees. I am very grateful to Keith Sutherland of Imprint Academic for being willing to take chances other publishers will not take, and to Dr Robert Grant of Glasgow University for pointing me in his direction.

    Gordon Graham

    King’s College

    University of Aberdeen

    April 2002

    Introduction

    The title of this book has been chosen in allusion to John Henry Newman’s The Idea of a University. Newman’s essay was originally a series of lectures (or ‘Discourses’) delivered in Dublin in advance of the establishment of the Catholic University of Ireland in 1854. The essay first appeared as a set of pamphlets, soon after to be bound together and is still in print.

    The context for these lectures was a dispute which has no interest for most people today. Newman was providing a theoretical defence of the Irish Catholic hierarchy’s objection to the secular university colleges established in Ireland by the British Government in 1845 (though ironically this Catholic alternative eventually formed the basis of the National University of Ireland which united most of these same colleges). He mounts his defence on the strength of a thesis that is unlikely to meet with much support in contemporary universities, namely the impossibility of a secular, non-religious university education. As a consequence of this context, a central part of his argument has to do with the role and teaching of theology, a subject absent from the curricula of most modern British universities, and a minority subject where it is still taught. A further, substantial part of the lectures is devoted to reconciling the authority of the church with the investigations of modern science, another topic likely to be of limited interest today. Yet despite these important differences between Newman’s time and ours, The Idea of a University (especially Discourses V, VI and VII) still has things to say that are relevant to thinking about contemporary universities.

    More surprising than this continuing relevance, however, is the fact that in the century and a half since Newman wrote, his book has had no significant successor, even though monumental changes have taken place in universities during this same period. Indeed, more striking still is the fact that Newman’s is one of very few attempts ever made to think directly about the nature and purpose of a university. Given the age of the institution, and its importance to the intellectual and cultural life of this country over many centuries, this is a remarkable fact.

    There is one recent exception to this generalization, namely The New Idea of a University by Duke Maskell and Ian Robinson (London, 2001) which expressly discusses Newman, and deplores what it sees as a radical departure among contemporary universities from the ‘old’ idea. According to Maskell and Robinson in recent times [t]he university has been remade not in defiance of Newman but in indifference to him. But he says things that, if anybody paid attention to them, could not fail to kill instantly our new orthodoxy about the universities making us rich (Maskell and Robinson 2001: 25). Now, whatever the justice of their complaint, the fact is as I have just suggested - the context of Newman’s lectures was inevitably quite different to that of the present day. His Discourses undertake to characterize and defend what has come to be known as a liberal education. Though often cited in defence of more arcane subjects by university teachers, the actual influence that is to be attributed to his book has probably been overestimated. It is the traditional American liberal arts college that has come closest to Newman’s ideal, not the universities of Britain from whose experience his reflections arose. There is to my mind a dangerous romanticism in thinking that once upon a time British universities were suitably Newmanesque until the arrival of utilitarian Philistines, and Maskell and Robinson constantly run the risk of falling into this trap. In several places Newman’s ‘arguments’ are weak, as it seems to me, and to call upon them is unlikely to kill instantly the ideas that have won favour in the minds of many modern academics. Nevertheless there is something important to emulate in Newman’s enterprise - the spirit of inquiring clearly and critically into the very idea of a university and its value.

    The purpose of this book, then, is not to review or revitalize Newman’s arguments, though, since a number of the themes he addresses are still topical, I shall refer to some of his claims from time to time in the chapters that follow. Nor is it my aim to deplore the present and lament the past, a charge that might not wholly inaccurately be brought against Maskell and Robinson. Rather, my purpose in writing is to draw attention to a number of interrelated issues that are of considerable contemporary significance, to examine them in a sustained way and, it is to be hoped, begin a discussion that is long overdue - namely some inquiry into how we should regard universities and what it is reasonable to expect from them.

    Such a discussion (as I shall conduct it) is an exercise in two branches of philosophy - philosophy of education and applied philosophy. Interestingly, the recent history of both is singularly different. The philosophy of education, after a short lively period dominated by R.S. Peters, is in the doldrums. Even at its height, the philosophy of higher education never got much attention. By contrast, applied philosophy, the attempt to relate philosophical questions to social and moral issues, has flourished in recent years as never before. It has largely been concerned with ethical questions and with public issues related, in one way or another, to the question of social justice. Yet there is good reason to think, as I hope to show, that the traditional questions of philosophy of education, which have to do with learning, understanding, science, practical training and the value of knowledge, have important implications in the sphere of social policy with respect to higher education.

    The task of exploring these implications is difficult for two reasons. Any discussion of the nature and conduct of universities at the present time runs the risk of being pigeon-holed, that is, of being automatically bracketed with one of two opposed positions. On the one side there is the modernizer who believes that old ideas must be abandoned in the face of the necessity to deal with ‘reality’, and on the other there is the ‘traditionalist’ who believes that every such move sells the pass on values and institutions that are vital to civilization as we know it, and to which we should fight to return. The New Idea of a University might plausibly be said by its critics to fall into the latter camp.

    Yet these two views are caricatures of each other, and if serious thinking about universities and the policies which should govern them is to take place, it is essential that the straight-jacketed thinking this sort of dichotomy inevitably induces be abandoned. Both contemporary conditions and educational history are more complex than would favour either position - and hence the sort of thinking that needs to be done must be more complex too. This very complexity, however, gives rise to the second difficulty. The variety of topics that need to be considered if we are to introduce any measure of coherence into thinking about the modern university is very considerable. It is necessary to sketch the history of the institution, to consider the ideas of higher education and academic research, to record recent social trends, to look at a spectrum of social policies, to explore cultural images, to examine educational methods, and to review the economics of public finance. This range of tasks is somewhat daunting. Yet it is at heart, in my view, philosophical, and it is questions in the philosophy of education which must make the running.

    Such is the scope of these questions, however, that it is not possible to offer the last word on any of the topics under review. On the other hand, there is something to be said for sticking one’s head above the parapet and offering the first word. I am firmly convinced that though the topics with which this book deals are philosophical, they are also of public importance, and I have attempted to relate the relatively abstruse to the relatively practical. This is the mark of ‘applied’ philosophy. I also think that they have not been addressed in a sustained or measured way, and that doing so might contribute something towards ameliorating the confusion and, indeed, malaise, by which life in contemporary British universities is marred. At any rate this is something reasonable to attempt.

    Philosophy at its best is marked by clarity and rigour. There are topics that are not properly speaking those of philosophy, yet there are things about them that only a philosopher would, or could, say. The nature of a university is one of these. I hope that my professional mode of analytical thinking and writing has enabled me to preserve philosophy’s intellectual virtues in the exploration of the many issues which I believe need to be addressed. If I have, the book will have the merit of setting out certain questions, and some answers to them, in a manner which makes their debate more precise, and hence more profitable. At any rate this is my aim and, given the breadth of the subject, to have realised it is as much as could be reasonably wished for.

    1: A Very Short History of British Universities

    The Mediaeval University

    No one can say precisely when university education began in Britain. Although we know that Oxford was Britain’s first university, and was founded after Paris, Bologna and several others on the continent of Europe, we do not know exactly when ‘the clerks of Oxenford’ first started to study and teach. The early part of the twelfth century seems likely, perhaps because from 1167 English students were barred from attending the University of Paris. Certainly, by the end of the twelfth century, Oxford was established to a degree sufficient for it to be regarded as a distinct place of learning. Then in 1207, or thereabouts, some of the Oxford clerks migrated to Cambridge, and England’s second university began. Amazingly enough, it was over six hundred years before a third was founded, The two universities added very many constituent colleges over this long period, of course, but while in these colleges fellows taught and students learned, it was the universities that had the right to confer degrees. And of these, for the greater part of English educational history, there were only two.

    But the third university in the British Isles came into existence not so very long after, at St Andrews in Scotland. Started somewhere between 1411 and 1413, permission to found Scotland’s first university was given initially by the renegade Pope in Avignon, though readily confirmed by Rome when the schism which had resulted in the existence of two rival popes ended. In the course of the same century further universities were established at Glasgow (1451) and Aberdeen (1495) also by the express authority of the Pope. Both drew their inspiration from Europe, the first Principal of Aberdeen coming from the University of Paris. In 1583 the University of Edinburgh was founded. Edinburgh was different to all the rest, both North and South of the border, in that, though it was inspired by Presbyterianism, it was a civic rather than a religious foundation (and to this day has no college chapel). It was the City Fathers, not the Church Fathers who called it into existence and the Crown which gave it the authority to confer degrees. But before the end of the century there was one further religious foundation in Scotland. The Reformation brought about the establishment in Aberdeen in 1593 of a Protestant rival to King’s College, named Marischal College after the Protestant Earl Marischal of Scotland who was its creator, and for over two hundred and fifty years (until 1860) they remained separate universities, allowing Aberdonians to boast that their city had as many universities as the whole of England.

    A little earlier (1591) Dublin University, with just one college (Trinity) had come into existence, modeled closely on the Oxbridge pattern. As Ireland’s first and oldest university, it became a place of some distinction in its own right, being the alma mater of Oliver Goldsmith and Edmund Burke amongst others, though it never quite emerged from the shadow of Oxford. The fact that for the first three hundred years of its existence only Anglicans were allowed to attend it, gave it the image and reputation of both a representative and a bastion of the Protestant Ascendancy, which it retained until well after the Republic of Ireland had been established. As a consequence, though it was Ireland’s only university for 250 years, until very recently it was never really an Irish one.

    By the end of the sixteenth century, then, Britain had eight universities, five in Scotland, two in England, one in Ireland. It was over a hundred years before there were any more. With the exception of Edinburgh, they were all religious foundations, of greatly differing sizes. As in their continental counterparts, their founding subjects were Theology, Law and Arts and a large part of their purpose was to provide education originally designed for the professional classes of the middle ages. This was less true of Edinburgh and Dublin, and in all of them other interests and subjects

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1