Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Beyond Mechanical Markets: Asset Price Swings, Risk, and the Role of the State
Beyond Mechanical Markets: Asset Price Swings, Risk, and the Role of the State
Beyond Mechanical Markets: Asset Price Swings, Risk, and the Role of the State
Ebook394 pages4 hours

Beyond Mechanical Markets: Asset Price Swings, Risk, and the Role of the State

Rating: 2 out of 5 stars

2/5

()

Read preview

About this ebook

A powerful challenge to contemporary economics and a new agenda for global finance

In the wake of the global financial crisis that began in 2007, faith in the rationality of markets has lost ground to a new faith in their irrationality. The problem, Roman Frydman and Michael Goldberg argue, is that both the rational and behavioral theories of the market rest on the same fatal assumption—that markets act mechanically and economic change is fully predictable. In Beyond Mechanical Markets, Frydman and Goldberg show how the failure to abandon this assumption hinders our understanding of how markets work, why price swings help allocate capital to worthy companies, and what role government can and can't play.

The financial crisis, Frydman and Goldberg argue, was made more likely, if not inevitable, by contemporary economic theory, yet its core tenets remain unchanged today. In response, the authors show how imperfect knowledge economics, an approach they pioneered, provides a better understanding of markets and the financial crisis. Frydman and Goldberg deliver a withering critique of the widely accepted view that the boom in equity prices that ended in 2007 was a bubble fueled by herd psychology. They argue, instead, that price swings are driven by individuals' ever-imperfect interpretations of the significance of economic fundamentals for future prices and risk. Because swings are at the heart of a dynamic economy, reforms should aim only to curb their excesses.

Showing why we are being dangerously led astray by thinking of markets as predictably rational or irrational, Beyond Mechanical Markets presents a powerful challenge to conventional economic wisdom that we can't afford to ignore.

LanguageEnglish
Release dateFeb 7, 2011
ISBN9781400838189
Beyond Mechanical Markets: Asset Price Swings, Risk, and the Role of the State

Related to Beyond Mechanical Markets

Related ebooks

Finance & Money Management For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Beyond Mechanical Markets

Rating: 2 out of 5 stars
2/5

1 rating0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Beyond Mechanical Markets - Roman Frydman

    (2010).

    PART I

    The Critique

    Indeed, the chief point was already seen by those remarkable anticipators of modern economics, the Spanish schoolmen of the sixteenth century, who emphasized that what they called the mathematical price depended on so many particular circumstances that it could never be known to man but was known only to God.

    —Friedrich A. Hayek,

    The Pretence of Knowledge, Nobel Lecture

    1

    The Invention of Mechanical Markets

    ALTHOUGH THE raison d'être for financial markets implies that they cannot assess asset values perfectly, over the last four decades of the twentieth century, economists developed an approach to macroeconomics and finance that implied that financial markets allocate society's capital almost perfectly. To reach this conclusion, economists constructed probabilistic models that portray an imaginary world in which nonroutine change ceases to be important; indeed, it becomes irrelevant.

    An economic theory of the world that starts from the premise that nothing genuinely new ever happens has a particularly simple—and thus attractive—mathematical structure: its models are made up of fully specified mechanical rules that are supposed to capture individual decisionmaking and market outcomes at all times: past, present, and future. As one of the pioneers of contemporary macroeconomics put it, I prefer to use the term ‘theory'…[as] something that can be put on a computer and run…the construction of a mechanical artificial world populated by interacting robots that economics typically studies (Lucas, 2002, p. 21).

    To portray individuals as robots and markets as machines, contemporary economists must select one overarching rule that relates asset prices and risk to a set of fundamental factors, such as corporate earnings, interest rates, and overall economic activity, in all time periods. Only then can participants' decisionmaking process be put on a computer and run. But this portrayal grossly distorts our understanding of financial markets. After all, participants' forecasts drive the movements of prices and risk in these markets, and market participants revise their forecasting strategies at times and in ways that they themselves cannot ascertain in advance.

    To be sure, with insightful selection of the causal variables and a bit of luck, a fully predetermined model might adequately describe—according to statistical or other, less stringent, criteria—the past relationship between causal variables and aggregate outcomes in a selected historical period. As time passes, however, market participants eventually revise their forecasting strategies, and the social context changes in ways that cannot be fully foreseen by anyone. The collapse of the hedge fund Long Term Capital Management in 1998, and the failure of ratings agencies to provide adequate risk assessments in the run-up to the financial crisis that began in 2007, shows that models assuming that the future follows mechanically from the past eventually become inadequate. Trading in financial markets cannot, in the end, be reduced to mere financial engineering.

    ECONOMISTS' RATIONALITY OR MARKETS?

    Ignoring such considerations, contemporary macroeconomic and finance theory developed models of asset prices and risk as if asset markets, and the broader economy, could be adequately portrayed as a fully predetermined mechanical system. And, recognizing that reducing economics and finance to engineering requires some justification, contemporary economists developed a mechanistic notion of rationality that they then claimed provided plausible individual foundations for their mechanical models.

    Lucas hypothesized that the predictions produced by an economist's own fully predetermined model of market outcomes adequately characterizes the forecasts of rational market participants. The normative label of rationality has fostered the belief, among economists and noneconomists alike, that this so-called Rational Expectations Hypothesis (REH) really does capture the way reasonable people think about the future.

    Of course, hypothesizing that any fully predetermined model can adequately characterize reasonable decisionmaking in markets is fundamentally bogus. Assuming away nonroutine change cannot magically eliminate its importance in real-world markets. Profit-seeking participants simply cannot afford to ignore such change and steadfastly adhere to any overarching forecasting strategy, even if economists refer to it as rational.¹

    The Soviet experiment in central planning clearly shows that even the vast and brutal powers of the state cannot compel history to follow a fully predetermined path.² Change that cannot be fully foreseen, whether political, economic, institutional, or cultural, is the essence of any society's historical development.³

    Such arguments were, however, completely ignored. Once an economist hypothesizes that his model generates an exact account of how an asset's prospects are related to available information about fundamental factors and adopts the Rational Expectations Hypothesis as the basis for rational trading decisions, it is only a short step to a model of the rational market.

    Such a model implies that prices reflect the true prospects of the underlying assets nearly perfectly. An economist merely needs to assume that the market is populated solely by this sort of rational individuals, who all have equal access to information when making trading decisions. In the context of such a model, competition…among the many [rational] intelligent participants [would result in an] efficient market at any point in time. In such a market, the actual price of a security will be a good estimate of its…[‘true'] value (Fama, 1965, p. 56).

    Economists and many others thought that the theory of the rational market provided the scientific underpinning for their belief that markets populated by rational individuals set asset prices correctly on average. In fact, this theory is the proverbial castle in the air: it rests on the demonstrably false premises that the future unfolds mechanically from the past, and that market participants believe this as well.

    WAS MILTON FRIEDMAN REALLY UNCONCERNED

    ABOUT ASSUMPTIONS?

    Fully predetermined models presume that nonroutine change can be completely ignored when searching for adequate accounts of outcomes. These models offer an extreme response to the daunting challenge that such change poses for economic analysis. In contrast, relying on largely narrative analysis, Hayek, Knight, Keynes, and their contemporaries focused on the inextricable connection between nonroutine change, imperfect knowledge, and the pursuit of profit in capitalist economies.

    As insightful and rich as these narrative accounts were, most contemporary economists probably felt that jettisoning them in favor of the clarity and transparent logic of mathematical models was a move in the right direction. After all, any explanation of the real world, let alone of the highly complex interdependence between individuals and the market, must necessarily abstract radically from its numerous characteristics. Even the detailed narrative accounts of Hayek, Keynes, Knight, and others left out many features of this interdependence.

    But to instruct economists to embrace models that are constrained to portray capitalist economies as a world populated by interacting robots was not merely to call for more clarity and transparent logic in economic analysis. Economists were being asked to adopt an approach that went well beyond useful abstraction, because what it left out was actually the essential feature of capitalist economies.

    Of course, most economists would readily agree that assuming away the importance of nonroutine change is not realistic. But they nonetheless cling to this core assumption in the belief that it transforms economics into an exact science. They also would agree that the Rational Expectations Hypothesis is not realistic, often describing it as a convenient assumption.⁴ When confronted with criticism that their assumptions are unrealistic, contemporary economists brush it off by invoking the dictum put forth by Milton Friedman (1953, p. 23) in his well-known essay on economic methodology: theory cannot be tested by the ‘realism' of its assumptions.

    Our criticism, however, is not that the core assumptions of the contemporary approach are unrealistic. Useful scientific models are those that abstract from features of reality. The hope is that the omitted considerations really are relatively unimportant to understanding the phenomenon. The fatal flaw of contemporary economic models is their omission of considerations that play a crucial role in driving the outcomes that they seek to explain.

    In fact, at no point did Friedman suggest that economists should not be concerned about the inadequacy of their models' assumptions.⁵ Indeed, at the time that he wrote his essay, examining assumptions was an important aspect of the discourse among economists. Friedman (1953, p. 23) recounted a strong tendency that we all have to speak of the assumptions of a theory and to compare assumptions of alternative theories. There is too much smoke for there to be no fire

    Consequently, Friedman devoted substantial parts of his essay to an effort aimed at reconciling a strong tendency among economists of his time to discuss assumptions with his main conclusion that a theory cannot be tested by the realism of its assumptions. Using a variety of arguments and examples, he reiterated the essential point: an economist's success in devising a model that is likely to predict reasonably well crucially depends on the assumptions that are selected to construct it. As Friedman (1953, p. 26) put it, "The particular assumptions termed ‘crucial' are selected [at least in part] on the grounds of…intuitive plausibility, or capacity to suggest, if only by implication, some of the considerations that are relevant in judging or applying the

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1